Facs

Tillich Lectures

Transcript

[601] dimension of a. It loses the bof ultimate concern step by step, becomes shallow and empty, and then becomes desperate about itself. This is the moment where new heteronomies enter into the vacuum, as for instance in the modern time, the c heteronomies coming from the d; or being represented still by the churches in their authoritarian or e ways of thought. Now if this is so, then nothing is more urgent than the question: is there something beyond the alternative of a repressive f and an emptying g? To this fundamental question, l answer: Yes, there is something; let's give it the name ''theonomy''--it is not a quite adequate name, but it is so well related to ''heteronomy'' and ''autonomy'' that one might use it. But then one must define it. It is not a divine law represented by the Church and put upon the h--that would be heteronomy. i is autonomy, but aware of its depth-dimension; is autonomy moving on the basis of an ultimate concern. Now the question of course is: how far is this possible? Is it possible at all? It IS possible, if we look at human j. It is never completely actualized. There is always the one or the other predominant, either the autonomous element or the heteronomy element. In any case, we have periods of history in which the forms of life, the kforms, the l forms, the m forms, expressed ultimate concern, with or against the churches. And such periods, as for instance the archaic-Greek n period, or the 11th or 12th centuries in the o, or the p period--such periods are, in some way, theonomous. They do not separate the ultimate concern and the preliminary concerns. They see, in their preliminary concerns, in the

Register

aUltimacy
bSubstance
cTotalitarian
dState
eFundamentalism
fHeteronomy
gAutonomy
hCulture
iTheonomy
jHistory
kArt
lCognitive
mPolitics
nPhilosophy
oMiddle_Ages
pReformation

Entities

Keywords

TL-0606.pdf